WorldCat Identities

Simplicius of Cilicia

Overview
Works: 498 works in 1,960 publications in 5 languages and 21,747 library holdings
Genres: History  Criticism, interpretation, etc 
Roles: Author, Annotator, cnm, Editor, Commentator for written text, Commentator, Author of introduction, Creator, Other, Translator
Classifications: Q151.A8, 530
Publication Timeline
.
Most widely held works about Simplicius
 
moreShow More Titles
fewerShow Fewer Titles
Most widely held works by Simplicius
Simplicius on Aristotle's Physics 6 by Simplicius( Book )

18 editions published between 1988 and 2014 in English and held by 510 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Book Six of Aristotle's Physics, which concerns the continuum, shows Aristotle at his best. It contains his attack on atomism which forced subsequent Greek and Islamic atomists to reshape their views entirely. It also elaborates Zeno's paradoxes of motion and the famous paradoxes of stopping and starting. This is the first translation into any modern language of Simplicius' commentary on Book Six. Simplicius, the greatest ancient authority on Aristotle's Physics whose works have survived to the present, lived in the sixth century A.D. He produced detailed commentaries on several of Aristotle's works. Those on the Physics, which alone come to over 1300 pages in the original Greek, preserve not only a centuries-old tradition of ancient scholarship on Aristotle but also fragments of lost works by other thinkers, including both the Presocratic philosophers and such Aristotalians as Eudemus, Theophrastus and Alexander. The Physics contains some of Aristotle's best and most enduring work, and Simplicius' commentaries are essential to an understanding of it. This volume makes the commentary on Book Six accessible at last to all scholars, whether or not they know classical Greek. It will be indispensible for students of classical philosophy, and especially of Aristotle, as well as for those interested in philosophical thought of late antiquity. It will also be welcomed by students of the history of ideas and philosophers interested in problem mathematics and motion."--Bloomsbury Publishing
Commentaire sur le Manuel d'Epictète by Simplicius( Book )

53 editions published between 1995 and 2003 in 3 languages and held by 460 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

On Aristotle's Physics 7 by Simplicius( Book )

19 editions published between 1994 and 2015 in English and Undetermined and held by 389 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Book 7 of Aristotle's Physics - once regarded as merely an undeveloped early version of Book 8 - has recently attracted renewed interest. Differences of opinion concerning its importance are as old as Aristotle's text, and Simplicius' commentary, written in the sixth century A.D., is an indispensable tool for understanding Book 7. Charles Hagen here gives the English reader access to this commentary for the first time." "Among the most important aspects of the commentary are Simplicius' explanation of the interconnections among the chapters of Book 7 and his references to a more extensive second version of Aristotle's text than the one that survives today. Acknowledging that Book 8 offers a more precise discussion of the subject covered in Book 7, the case for a prime mover, Simplicius both identifies ways in which Book 7 reveals Aristotle's acumen and clarifies its relationship to the other books in the Physics."--BOOK JACKET
On Aristotle's Physics 2 by Simplicius( Book )

25 editions published between 1996 and 2014 in English and Undetermined and held by 373 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Book 2 of the Physics is arguably the best introduction to Aristotle's ideas. It defines nature and distinguishes natural science from mathematics. Book 2 introduces the seminal idea of four causes, or four modes of explanation. It defines chance, but rejects a theory of chance and natural selection in favour of purpose in nature. To these riches Simplicius, writing in the sixth century A.D., adds his own considerable contribution. Seeing Aristotle's God as a creator, he discusses how nature relates to soul, adds Stoic and Neoplatonist causes to Aristotle's list of four, and questions the likeness of cause to effect. He discusses missing a great evil or a great good by a hairsbreadth and considers whether animals act from reason or natural instinct. He also preserves a Posidonian discussion of mathematical astronomy."--Publisher description
On Aristotle's On the soul 1.1-2.4 by Simplicius( Book )

22 editions published between 1995 and 2014 in English and Undetermined and held by 364 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

Simplicius' On Aristotle's "On the Soul 1.1-2.4" is a major source for late Neoplatonist theories of thought and sense perception and offers considerable insight into an important area of Aristotelian philosophy. The present volume is the only English translation of the commentary and affords its readers the opportunity to consider the question of its disputed authorship. While most scholars attribute authorship of On Aristotle's "On the Soul 1.1-2.4" to Simplicius, some have judged it to be the work of Priscian, or of another philosopher. The commentary discusses the first half of On the Soul, which comprises Aristotle's survey of his predecessors' views, as well as his own account of the nature of the soul
On Aristotle's "Categories 5-6" by Simplicius( Book )

30 editions published between 2000 and 2014 in English and held by 363 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Chapters 5 and 6 of Aristotle's Categories describe his first two categories, Substance and Quantity. It is usually thought that Plotinus attacked Aristotle's Categories, but that Porphyry and Iamblichus restored it to the curriculum once and for all. However, Frans de Haas stresses that Porphyry drew much of his defense of Aristotle from Plotinus' critical discussion." "Simplicius' commentary is the most comprehensive account of the debate on the validity of Aristotle's Categories. Simplicius discusses where the differentia of a species (for instance, the rationality of humans) fits into the scheme of categories. Another is why Aristotle elevates the category of Quantity to second place, above the category of Quality. Further, de Haas shows how Simplicius arrives at multiple definitions of "universal" to solve some of the problems."--Jacket
Corollaries on place and time by Simplicius( Book )

20 editions published between 1992 and 2014 in English and Undetermined and held by 349 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Is there such a thing as three-dimensional space? Is space inert or dynamic? Is the division of time into past, present and future real? Does the whole of time exist all at once? Does it progress smoothly or by discontinuous leaps? Simplicius surveys ideas about place and time from the preceding thousand years of Greek Philosophy and reveals the extraordinary ingenuity of the late Neoplatonist theories, which he regards as marking a substantial advance on all previous ideas."--Bloomsbury Publishing
On Aristotle's Physics 5 by Simplicius( Book )

23 editions published between 1997 and 2014 in English and held by 327 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Simplicius, the greatest surviving ancient authority on Aristotle's Physics, lived in the sixth century A.D. He produced detailed commentaries on several of Aristotle's works. Those on the Physics, which alone come to over 1,300 pages in the original Greek, preserve a centuries-old tradition of ancient scholarship on Aristotle. In Physics Book 5 Aristotle lays down some of the principles of his dynamics and theory of change. What does not count as a change: change of relation? the flux of time? There is no change of change, yet acceleration is recognised. Aristotle defines 'continuous', 'contact', and 'next', and uses these definitions in discussing when we can claim that the same change or event is still going on."--Publisher description
On Aristotle's "On the Soul 3.1-5" by Simplicius( Book )

18 editions published between 1999 and 2014 in English and held by 307 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"In On the Soul 3. 1-5, Aristotle goes beyond the five senses to the general functions of sense perception, the imagination and the so-called active intellect, the identity of which was still a matter of controversy in the time of Thomas Aquinas." "In his commentary on Aristotle's text, 'Simplicius' insists that the intellect in question is not something transcendental, but the human rational soul. He denies both Plotinus' view that a part of the soul has never descended from uninterrupted contemplation of the Platonic Forms, and Proclus' view that the soul cannot be changed in its substance through embodiment." "Addressing the vexed question of authorship, H.J. Blumenthal concludes that the commentary was written neither by Simplicius nor Priscian. In a novel interpretation, he suggests that if Priscian had any hand in this commentary, it might have been as editor of notes from Simplicius' lectures."--Jacket
On Aristotle's "Categories 9-15" by Simplicius( Book )

19 editions published between 1999 and 2014 in English and held by 302 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

This is one in a series of translations with introductions, copius notes and comprehensive indexes. It fills an important gap in the history of European thought
On Aristotle's "Physics 8.6-10" by Simplicius( Book )

18 editions published between 2001 and 2014 in English and held by 273 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Aristotle's Physics is about the causes of motion and culminates in a proof that God is needed as the ultimate cause of motion. Aristotle argues that things in motion need to be moved by something other than themselves - he rejects Plato's self-movers. On pain of regress, there must be an unmoved mover. If this unmoved mover is to cause motion eternally, it needs infinite power. It cannot, then, be a body, since bodies, being of finite size, cannot house infinite power. The unmoved mover is therefore an incorporeal God." "Simplicius reveals that his teacher, Ammonius, harmonized Aristotle with Plato to counter Christian charges of pagan disagreement, by making Aristotle's God a cause not only of beginningless movement, but also of beginningless existence of the universe. Eternal existence, no less than eternal motion, calls for an infinite, and hence incorporeal, force. This anti-Christian interpretation turned Aristotle's God from a thinker into a certain kind of Creator, and so helped to make Aristotle's God acceptable to Saint Thomas Aquinas in the thirteenth century."--Jacket
On Aristotle's "Categories 7-8" by Simplicius( Book )

18 editions published between 2002 and 2014 in English and held by 273 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"In his discussion of Quality, Aristotle reports a debate on whether justice admits of degrees, or whether only the possession of justice does so. Simplicius reports the further development of this controversy in terms of whether justice admits a range or latitude (platos). This debate helped to inspire the medieval idea of latitude of forms, which thus goes back much further than is commonly recognized - at least as far in the past as Plato and Aristotle."--Jacket
On Aristotle's "Physics 3" by Simplicius( Book )

15 editions published between 2002 and 2013 in English and held by 261 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Aristotle's Physics Book 3 covers two subjects: the definition of change and the finitude of the universe. Change enters into the very definition of nature as an internal source of change. Change receives two definitions in chapters 1 and 2, as involving the actualisation of the potential or of the changeable. Alexander of Aphrodisias is reported as thinking that the second version is designed to show that Book 3, like Book 5, means to disqualify change in relations from being genuine change. Aristotle's successor Theophrastus, we are told, and Simplicius himself, prefer to admit relational change. Chapter 3 introduces a general causal principle that the activity of the agent causing change is in the patient undergoing change, and that the causing and undergoing are to be counted as only one activity, however different in definition. Simplicius points out that this paves the way for Aristotle's God who moves the heavens, while admitting no motion in himself. It is also the basis of Aristotle's doctrine, central to Neoplatonism, that intellect is one with the objects it contemplates. In defending Aristotle's claim that the universe is spatially finite, Simplicius has to meet Archytas' question, "What happens at the edge?". He replies that, given Aristotle's definition of place, there is nothing, rather than an empty place, beyond the furthest stars, and one cannot stretch one's hand into nothing, nor be prevented by nothing. But why is Aristotle's beginningless universe not temporally infinite? Simplicius answers that the past years no longer exist, so one never has an infinite collection."--Bloomsbury Publishing
On Aristotle's "On the heavens 2.1-9" by Simplicius( Book )

22 editions published between 2002 and 2014 in English and held by 251 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Aristotle believed that the outermost stars are carried round us on a transparent sphere. There are directions in the universe and a preferred direction of rotation. The sun moon and planets are carried on different revolving spheres. The spheres and celestial bodies are composed of an everlasting fifth element, which has none of the ordinary contrary properties like heat and cold which could destroy it, but only the facility for uniform rotation. But this creates problems as to how the heavenly bodies create light, and, in the case of the sun, heat. The value of Simplicius' commentary on On the Heavens 2, 1-9 lies partly in its preserving the lost comments of Alexander and in Simplicius' controversy with him. The two of them discuss not only the problem mentioned, but also whether soul and nature move the spheres as two distinct forces or as one. Alexander appears to have simplified Aristotle's system of 55 spheres down to seven, and some hints may be gleaned as to whether, simplifying further, he thinks there are seven ultimate movers, or only one."--Bloomsbury Publishing
Simplicius On Aristotle's "On the Heavens 1.5-9" by Simplicius( Book )

24 editions published between 2002 and 2015 in English and held by 246 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Aristotle argues in On the Heavens 1.5-7 that there can be no infinitely large body, and in 1.8-9 that there cannot be more than one physical world. As a corollary in 1.9, he infers that there is no place, vacuum or time beyond the outermost stars. As one argument in favour of a single world, he argues that his four elements, earth, air, fire and water, have only one natural destination apiece. Moreover they accelerate as they approach it and acceleration cannot be unlimited. However, the Neoplatonist Simplicius, who wrote the commentary translated here in the sixth century AD, tells us that this whole world view was to be rejected by Strato, the third head of Aristotle's school. At the same time, he tells us the different theories of acceleration in Greek philosophy."--Bloomsbury Publishing
On Aristotle on the heavens 1.3-4 by Simplicius( Book )

8 editions published between 2011 and 2014 in English and held by 137 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

On Aristotle Physics 1.3-4 by Simplicius( Book )

13 editions published between 2010 and 2014 in English and held by 131 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"In this volume Simplicius is dealing with Aristotle's account of the Presocratics, and for many of them he is our chief or even sole authority. He quotes at length from Melissus, Parmenides and Zeno, sometimes from their original works but also from later writers from Plato onwards, drawing particularly on Alexander's lost commentary on Aristotle's Physics and on Porphyry. Much of his approach is just scholarly, but in places he reveals his Neoplatonist affiliation and attempts to show the basic agreement among his predecessors in spite of their apparent differences."--Publisher description
On Aristotle On the heavens 1.2-3 by Simplicius( Book )

12 editions published between 2010 and 2014 in English and held by 126 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

This is the first complete translation into a modern language of the first part of the pagan Neoplatonist Simplicius of Cilicia's commentary on Aristotle's argument that the world neither came to be nor will perish
On Aristotle Physics 8.1-5 by Simplicius( Book )

11 editions published between 2012 and 2014 in English and held by 101 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

In this commentary on Aristotle Physics book eight, chapters one to five, the sixth-century philosopher Simplicius quotes and explains important fragments of the Presocratic philosophers, provides the fragments of his Christian opponent Philoponus' Against Aristotle On the Eternity of the World, and makes extensive use of the lost commentary of Aristotle's leading defender, Alexander of Aphrodisias. This volume contains an English translation of Simplicius' important commentary, as well as a detailed introduction, explanatory notes and a bibliography
On Aristotle Physics 1.5-9 by Simplicius( Book )

9 editions published between 2012 and 2014 in English and held by 101 WorldCat member libraries worldwide

"Simplicius' greatest contribution in his commentary on Aristotle on 'Physics' 1.5-9 lies in his treatment of matter. He starts with a valuable elucidation of what Aristotle means by 'principle' and 'element' in 'Physics'. Simplicius' own conception of matter is of a quantity that is utterly diffuse because of its extreme distance from its source, the Neoplatonic One, and he tries to find this conception both in Plato's account of space and in a stray remark of Aristotle's. Finally, he rejects the Manichaean view that matter is evil and answers a Christian objection that to make matter imperishable is to put it on a level with God"--Publisher's description, p. [2] of dust jacket
 
moreShow More Titles
fewerShow Fewer Titles
Audience Level
0
Audience Level
1
  Kids General Special  
Audience level: 0.40 (from 0.08 for On Aristot ... to 0.88 for Das Anaxag ...)

WorldCat IdentitiesRelated Identities
Simplicius on Aristotle's Physics 6
Alternative Names

controlled identityPseudo-Simplicius

Cilicius, Simplicius ca. 6.Jh.

Pseudo-Simplicius ca. 6.Jh.

Simplici de Cilícia

Simplício

Simplicio 0490?-0560?

Simplicio ca. 6.Jh.

Simplício da Cilícia

Simplicio de Cilicia

Simplicio filosofo e matematico bizantino

Simplicius

Simplicius 6e eeuw of Cilicia

Simplicius Aristotelicus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Atheniensis

Simplicius Atheniensis ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius aus Kilikien

Simplicius aus Kilikien ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Aristotelicus

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Atheniensis

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh aus Kilikien

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Cilicius

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh de Cilicia

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Neapolitanus

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Neoplatonicus

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Neuplatoniker

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh of Cilicia

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Perepateticus

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Peripateticus

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Philosoph

Simplicius ca. 6.Jh Philosophus

Simplicius Cilicius

Simplicius Cilicius 500-talet e.Kr

Simplicius de Cilicia

Simplicius de Cilicia ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Neapolitanus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Neoplatonicus

Simplicius Neoplatonicus 500-talet e.Kr

Simplicius Neoplatonicus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Neoplatonicus sec. VI

Simplicius Neuplatoniker ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius of Cilicia

Simplicius, of Cilicia, 6e eeuw

Simplicius of Cilicia ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius of Cilicia činný 6. století

Simplicius of Cilicia disciple of Ammonius Hermiae and Damascius, and one of the last of the Neoplatonists

Simplicius, of Cilícia, s. VI

Simplicius of Cilicius.

Simplicius Perepateticus

Simplicius Perepateticus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Peripateticus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius Philosoph

Simplicius Philosoph ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius philosophe antique

Simplicius Philosophus ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius, Pseudo- ca. 6.Jh.

Simplicius s. VI of Cilícia

Simplicius van Cilicië filosoof uit Byzantijnse Rijk (490-560)

Simplikij

Simplikio of Cilicia

Simplikios.

Simplíkios 0490?-0560?

Simplikios 500-talet e.Kr

Simplikios approxomately 490-560 ho Kilix

Simplikios approxomately 490-560 of Cilicia

Simplikios ca. 6.Jh.

Simplikios ca. 6.Jh von Kilikien

Simplikios, de Cilícia, s. VI

Simplikios de Cilicie

Simplikios, ho Kilix, approxomately 490-560

Simplikios of Cilicia

Simplikios, of Cilicia, approxomately 490-560

Simplikios Philosoph der Antike

Simplikios s. VI de Cilícia

Simplikios von Kilikien ca. 6.Jh.

Simplikiou.

Simplikkíos

Simplikos

Sinplizio Ziliziakoa

Symplicjusz z Cylicji

Σιμπλίκιος

Σιμπλίκιος 0490?-0560?

Σιμπλίκιος approxomately 490-560 ὁ Κίλιξ

Σιμπλίκιος, ὁ Κίλιξ, approxomately 490-560

Симпликий

Симпликий Киликийский

Симпликий ок.490-560

Симплиций

سیمپلیکیوس

キリキアのシンプリキオス

Languages
Covers
Commentaire sur le Manuel d'EpictèteOn Aristotle's Physics 7On Aristotle's Physics 2On Aristotle's On the soul 1.1-2.4On Aristotle's "Categories 5-6"On Aristotle's Physics 5On Aristotle's "On the Soul 3.1-5"On Aristotle's "Categories 9-15"